2023-10-20
“Almost a century ago, it was remarked by a Professor Aikins that the science of psychology frequently manifests what he called ‘the jingle fallacy,’ a circumstance wherein two things that are quite different may be labeled equivalently, and thus the unwary may consider them interchangeable” (Block, 1995, p. 209)
The jangle fallacy: “two separate words or expressions covering in fact the same basic situation, but sounding different, as though they were in truth different” (Kelley, 1927, p. 64)
Thorndike (1904); Kelley (1927); Block (1995)
” … at least three views of autonomy appear to be present in the current autonomy literature [and] autonomy measures are not assessing the same construct” (Hmel & Pincus, 2002)
All three are labeled “autonomy” in the literature!
Hmel & Pincus (2002)
“Grit is not only an excellent predictor of success and performance but also the secret to success” - Duckworth et al. (2007)
These jingle and jangle fallacies waste scientific time:
paraphrased from Block (1995)
Collect candidates for the jingle and the jangle fallacy that you encountered during your studies.
Reminder
(We will discuss this model in detail in the next session)
See Borsboom et al. (2021). Theory Construction Methodology: A Practical Framework for Building Theories in Psychology. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 16(4), 756–766. https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691620969647
Phenomena: Stable and general features of the world in need of explanation. Can be understood as robust generalizations of patterns in empirical data. They are the explanatory targets for scientific theories. In psychology often called “effects”.
Data: Relatively direct observations. Refer to particular empirical patterns in concrete data sets rather than empirical generalizations (which would be phenomenona). Also called a “finding”.
See Borsboom et al. (2021). Theory Construction Methodology: A Practical Framework for Building Theories in Psychology. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 16(4), 756–766. https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691620969647
Data provide evidence for the existence of empirical phenomena: You generalize from one or more data sets with strong evidence to a general phenomenon.
Generalize to what? UTOS framework:
UTOS framework from Cronbach & Shapiro (1982); for an update to “M-STOUT”, including mechanims and time, see Findley et al. (2021).
To claim a (robust) phenomenon, you ideally need:
Probably most of psychological research is about establishing phenomena (disguised as “theories”).
Techniques used to detect data patterns:
See presentation of Denny Borsboom
Phenomena (once their existence has been established) predict similar data patterns in new data sets of the same operationalization (as in “direct replication”) and ideally also for new operationalizations (as in “conceptual replication”, changing more UTOS dimensions).
The risky shift phenomenon: A group’s decisions are riskier than the average of the individual decisions of members before the group met (i.e., the group discussion made individuals riskier).
See Westfall et al. (2015). Replicating Studies in Which Samples of Participants Respond to Samples of Stimuli. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 10(3), 390–399. https://doi.org/10.1177/1745691614564879
Questions for discussion (10 min.):
My take: It is a phenomenon (though a weak one), as it generalizes to new units (i.e., new participants) of the same operationalization. But the generalizability was much weaker than initially expected. It is a phenomenon of this specific stimulus set (outcome operationalization) and suggests certain types of research questions (e.g., “What is so specific to this stimulus set?”).
The concerns of the replication crisis typically referred to the relation between data and phenomena:
Doubts about phenomena propagate to theories: If there is no phenomenon to explain, any explanatory theory gets obsolete.
“We argue that a further cause of poor replicability is the often weak logical link between theories and their empirical tests. […] A strong link between theories and hypotheses is best achieved by formalizing theories as computational models.”
“Many of these proposals [i.e., method reforms] are helpful ideas for raising the standards of good research practice, primarily ensuring more trustworthy inferences on the empirical level of scientific inference — the level connecting observations to empirical generalizations. Our concern is that shoring up the strength of inferences on the empirical level does not by itself address deficits on the theory level — the level connecting empirical generalizations to theories.”Oberauer & Lewandowsky (2019)
Oberauer, K., & Lewandowsky, S. (2019). Addressing the theory crisis in psychology. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 26(5), 1596–1618. https://doi.org/10.3758/s13423-019-01645-2
See Eronen & Bringmann (2021); Slide adapted from Karolin Salmen, CC-BY
“Die Wahrheit liegt in der uns umgebenden Wirklichkeit unmittelbar vor uns. Diese können wir aber unverändert nicht gebrauchen. Eine lückenlose Beschreibung der Wirklichkeit wäre zugleich das wahrste und unnützste Ding von der Welt und gewiß keine Wissenschaft. Wir müssen der Wirklichkeit und damit der Wahrheit Gewalt antun, wenn wir sie wissenschaftlich verwerten wollen. Wir müssen die Unterscheidung von wesentlich und unwesentlich einführen, die es in der ganzen Natur nicht gibt. In ihr ist alles gleich wesentlich. Indem wir die uns wesentlich erscheinenden Zusammenhänge aufsuchen, ordnen wir zugleich den Stoff übersichtlich. Dann treiben wir Wissenschaft.”
(von Uexküll, 1909, S. 58)
von Uexküll, J. (1909). Umwelt und Innenwelt der Tiere. Berlin: J. Springer, p. 58. Quote found in Smaldino (2023)
Let’s not confuse the map with the territory!
paraphrased from Alfred Korzybski (1933) “Science and Sanity: An Introduction to Non-Aristotelian Systems and General Semantics”
„A language is like a map; it is not the territory represented, but it may be a good map or a bad map. If the map shows a different structure from the territory represented […] then the map is worse than useless, as it misinforms and leads astray. One who made use of it could never be certain of reaching his destination.“ (Korzybski, 1933, p. 375)
All models are wrong, but some models are useful.
Image CC-BY-SA 3.0 by DavidMCEddy (Wikimedia Commons)
“His design for a London underground railway was initially rejected as too revolutionary. Today, his idea has gained worldwide acceptance: Beck simplified the route (only horizontal, vertical and diagonal lines) and ignored exact distances.”
→ By omission of details (and making the map less realistic) the map got more useful!
Infographic and quote from Die ZEIT
How can we ensure that we do not create a purely self-referential system of symbols that does not refer to reality any more?
Of course we can play the mathematician’s game (and might have a lot of fun meanwhile). But ultimately, if we want to understand and explain the human psyche, we need to make sure that our constructs are grounded in reality.
How can this grounding happen?
Formal modeling in psychology - Empirisches Praktikum, Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München